CARBONE - The Nineties in
Italy
The 1998 International Conference concerning the heritage of
Merleau-Ponty and the first volume of Chiasmi International,
which is publishing the proceedings of this conference, testify
to the development of investigations devoted to Merleau-Ponty in
Italy since 1993. The revised translation of The Visible and
the Invisible in 1993 inaugurated a series of translations:
first the résumés of the courses from the Collège de
France, then the course notes themselves, which appeared in
France since 1995. If there were signs of this renewed interest
in the Eighties, notably the appearance of several issues of
journals and collections of commentaries, this was confirmed
beginning in 1993 the year Ettore Rocca's L'essere e il
giallo was published by means of several important
works. The works of Mauro Carbone (Il sensibile e l'eccedente)
and Paolo Gambazzi (L'occhio e il suo inconscio, which is
forthcoming) are based on the recently published course notes and
are interested more particularly in the relation of
Merleau-Ponty's ontology to aesthetics. But this interest in
ontology has nevertheless not eclipsed the interest in his
political thought, to which notably the translation of the
letters concerning the break with Sartre (by Enrica
Lisciani-Petrini and Daniela Calabrò) as well as the works of
Alessia Graziano, Stare a sinistra, and Antonio Martone, Verità
e comunità in Maurice Merleau-Ponty testify.
INVITTO - Italian Philosophers
Investigating Merleau-Ponty. A Short History of Three Generations
When one considers Merleau-Ponty's influence on contemporary
thought, one naturally turns to the evolution of Italian
philosophers investigating the French philosopher. We have three
generations of such philosophers. The Conference called
Merleau-Ponty vent'anni dopo (Lecce, 15-16 maggio
1981) gathered together the first and the second generation of
Italian commentators on Merleau-Ponty. Among this first
generation were Andrea Bonomi, Gian Luigi Brena, Aldo Masullo,
Sergio Moravia, Giuseppe Semerari. Because of other engagements,
Franco Fergnani, Renato Barilli, Xavier Tillette (Italian by
acquisition) and Silvana Folliero were absent. In particular, the
greatest absence was Enzo Paci, who had died some years before.
The second generation of commentators included Invitto, Ciro
Senofonte, Salvatore Costantino, Ornella Pompeo Faracovi and
Antonio Delogu. Shortly thereafter, Paolo Nepi and Anna Escher Di
Stefano joined the group. The last to enter the club
of Merleau-Ponty commentators were Sandro Mancini and Mauro
Carbone. In 1986, Invitto, Angela Ales Bello, Mario Signore,
Aniello Montano gave birth to the review Segni e
comprensione, starting from the idea of a section
dedicated to Merleau-Ponty of the Centro Italiano di
Ricerche Fenomenologiche. In 1996, in Milan, the
Società di studi su Maurice Merleau-Ponty was
founded by Ales Bello, Carbone, Invitto, Mancini and Dalla Vigna.
BARBARAS - Research Worthy of
the Name
In France, we are witnessing a new development in the
publication of Merleau-Ponty's works; in particular, three
volumes have appeared based on his lectures at the Collège de
France: his lectures concerning the concept of
Nature, the ones from 1959 to 1961 devoted to the
possibility of philosophy today, and his lectures
entitled Husserl at the Limits of Phenomenology.
Moreover, over the last ten years, several important books have
appeared which generally concern Merleau-Ponty's ontology or the
connection of his work to art and literature.
RAMIREZ - The Current
Situation Regarding Merleau-Ponty in Mexico (and in Argentina)
This report presents a concise overview of some papers
concerning Merleau-Ponty's philosophy in Mexico and Argentina. We
point out that the main aspect of the historical context for
these papers is Merleau-Ponty's influence on Emilio Uranga,
Mexican philosopher of the 1950's. Uranga was the first to
translate Phenomenology of Perception into Spanish and he
used phenomenological concepts in a critical
self-understanding of Mexican culture.
Then, we provide information about the work being done on
Merleau-Ponty in Argentina, in particular, the work of María
Lucrecia Rovaletti and María Luisa Pfeiffer. They both extend
the thought of the French philosopher, and phenomenology in
general, to the field of reflection and psychological and
psychiatric therapy.
Finally, we present a brief report on recent studies of
Merleau-Ponty in Mexico. It provides an account of the work of
Felipe Boburg, Professor at the Universidad Iberoamerica. It also
provides some information about an essay by Eduardo González di
Pierro and some basic ideas from two books written by Mario
Teodoro Ramírez (El quiasmo. Ensayo sobre la filosofia de
Merleau-Ponty and Cuerpo y arte. Para una estetica
merleaupontyana). The report concludes with some reflections
on how Merleau-Ponty's thought plays an important role in helping
us to understand the philosophical problems of
culture and inter-culture relations,
which are currently a principal subject of discussion in Mexico
and Latin America.
HIROSE - Merleau-Ponty at the
Limits of Modernity.
The Current Situation Concerning Studies on Merleau-Ponty
in Japan
Research on the philosophy of Merleau-Ponty has recently
become very active in Japan. The Japanese Merleau-Ponty Circle
has been acquiring a strong following since its establishment in
1993, and each year publishes the proceedings of its annual
meeting. In fact, all of Merleau-Ponty's writings have been
translated into Japanese (except the most recent lecture
courses). The reason that there is a growing interest in
Merleau-Ponty in Japan lies in the recognition of a certain
closeness between Merleau-Ponty's thought and Japanese thought.
But because there is no identity of traditional Japanese thought,
we have not really sought to root Merleau-Ponty in the firm soil
of our tradition. Instead, he has functioned as a sort of hinge (charnière)
between Japenese thought and French thought. In particular, the
recent investigations of Merleau-Ponty which center on
three areas in particular: his existentialism; his relation to
phenomenology; his relation to the human sciences (linguistics
and psychology) interrogate modernity not in order to
overcome it with post-modernism, but in order to place ourselves
at the internal limits of our modernity, internal limits which
are constantly displacing themselves.
WALDENFELS - Showing by
Words: Merleau-Ponty and the Linguistic Turn
Taking into account authors like Husserl, Heidegger,
Wittgenstein, Searle, Foucault, and Proust, the author tries to
show how Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology of language avoids the
alternative of either founding language in experience or
submitting experience to pre-existing linguistic structures and
rules. Showing by words means going between seeing
and speaking. This practice is stimulated by the paradox of
creative expression: speaking and writing means translating experience which however only becomes a text by the words it
evokes.
FERRARIS -
An intrinsic delay is hidden in every philosophy which intends
to determine the conditions of the possibility of experience: the
fact of experience itself. Transcendental or reflexive philosophy
does not strand itself in the sand of the unreflection from which
it must depart, that is, in the world; rather, it becomes
stranded in the pretense to define the experience starting from a
categorial dimension (the intellect) which would give it its
structure and make it possible at the same time. This is, in
brief, Merleau-Ponty's critique of Kant's philosophy; this is the
distance which divides phenomenology from any intellectual
reconstruction of the experience. It looks as though there can be
no point of agreement. In reality, if every form of being is in a
relationship with a subjectivity, a point upon which everyone
agrees, it would be necessary to understand the nature of this
subjectivity, that is, of a mind which is a thing between other
things and, as well, the condition of possibility of things.
Kant and Merelau-Ponty have the same attitude towards
psychology when they assert that the psyche represents not only
the possibility of an individual conscience, of an interiority,
but also the possibility of a universal science. In other words,
there is a psyche which is in and of the world
(that is, empirical), and a psyche which assures the constitution
of the world (that is, transcendental). But, its place is neither
empirical nor transcendental. Only if one liberates the psyche
from psychology, will one be able to have at the same time the
genesis (singular and sensible) of a world that does not happen
beyond the world, and the structure (universal and logical) of
the same world, which continues to have value beyond its real
genesis.
The Origin of the Truth, the title Merleau-Ponty
intended to give to The Visible and the Invisible,
concerns this difference and postulates, as one of the working
note says, a psyche which is not the one of
psychology.
BURKE - The Moral Power of the
Face of the Child
One of the major programs of UNICEF is called Adjustment
with a Human Face. It argues that any `model' for the
economic, industrial, and military development of third world
countries is justified only if it is applied with a human face,
with a profound moral sensitivity to the needs and rights of all
persons, as expressed in the face of the child. But the problem
which UNICEF confronts theoretically and practically in this
project would seeem to the be absence of, and the consequent need
for, a theory of the person as other on which to ground any claim
for the irreducible moral worth of children. If UNICEF were to
consult certain philosophies, such as British empiricism or
transcendental phenomenology, it may find only various and subtle
forms of the forgetfulness of the face of the child. The purpose
of the present essay is to focus on the writings of Maurice
Merleau-Ponty to see if we can find there a theory of
intersubjectivity and the foundation of human rights commensurate
with UNICEF's program for justice in our world. Such a theory, if
defensible, could constitute a significant aspect of the moral
heritage of Merleau-Ponty.
Merleau-Ponty offers two arguments for the person as other.
The first is a genetic argument, showing that otherness is a
constitutive dimension of personhood. The second is a
phenomenologicl argument centered on the reversibility of the
touching and the touched, of subject and object, wherein the
person as other is given in an originary way. These arguments are
examined in the light of two texts, written in the 1980's and
signed by Emmanuel Lévinas, which would question whether the
social relation and/or the ethical relation could be established
through intercorporeity. In these essays, Lévinas argues,
contrary to Merleau-Ponty, that the ethical relation is beyond
knowledge and within the modality of the gift. Is it to Lévinas,
then, rather than to Merleau-Ponty that UNICEF should turn to
find the philosophical framework adequate to its commitment to
the moral power of the face of the child?
Contrary to Lévinas, this essay purports to demonstrate that
a) Merleau-Ponty's reversibility schema does not preclude
affirmation of what is irreducibly Other in the other but
provides the common ground, lacking in Lévinas, for ethical
communication, and that b) if `the gift' is ever to be received,
the ethical relation will have to be conceived in terms of what
Merleau-Ponty understands by a humanism in extension
and Virtu. Thus, as part of its heritage,
Merleau-Ponty's thought can form the theoretical and practical
foundation for UNICEF's commitment to the moral power of the face
of the child.
CALABRO' - Maurice
Merleau-Ponty and the Labyrinth of Ontology
This paper is based on a series of unpublished manuscripts by
Merleau-Ponty. It refers especially to Esquisse ontologique (March, 1959 [?]), which is part of the manuscript entitled
Projets et plan du livre en vue depuis 1958 (boîte
III, D.M.O., B.N.F.), along with the annotations of September
23rd 1958, entitled Pour l'ontologie (boîte IV,
D.M.O., B.N.F.), and the annotations of the 6th and 7th of
October 1958 (boîte III, D.M.O., B.N.F.).
My choice of these particular documents from Merleau-Ponty's
unpublished works is not random. The philosophical journey starts
when Merleau-Ponty seems to break with his past considerations on
time, space, and movement, and thus on nature, man and being in
general. At this point, the relations between phenomenology,
ontology, and Gestaltpsychologie become intrinsically
linked.
Taking his inspiration from the criticism of 1) the science which encapsulates the idea of an in itself and of
the survol which assumes an absolute spectator; 2) the
reflective philosophy which replaces the possible with a sort
of actualism without taking into account the
unreflective and therefore passes directly to the One; 3) the
speculative concept which implies an in principle access to
being, Merleau-Ponty catches a glimpse of a solution to
the problem of the relation between the koinoV kosµoV and the
idioV kosµoV, a solution which is neither dualist nor
immanentist. We have to speak ce sera la tâche
de toute philosophie of the dédoublement
of one over the other.
As a matter of fact, as Merleau-Ponty says in Esquisse
ontologique, ce qui manque toujours c'est un monde
à plusieurs entrées: ou il y en a une, ou il y en a une infinité.
Il n'y en pas plusieurs (ce qui veut dire une en
plus ... Offenheit). The Befragung does
not consist in a reflection on the world or in an analysis of the world, but rather in a descent towards sense (a
world of flesh and blood), dévoilement du sens qui est
en même temps latence. It is a question of
acknowledging the essential double-vision of the Besinnung just at the stage when it becomes Ruckfrage. This enables
us to say that l'Offenheit de l'Umwelt et
l'ouverture du percevant sont même chose. C'est dans les choses
que se trouve le rapport dit de connaissance.
In a small marginal comment to L'interrogation de l'Etre
brut, Merleau-Ponty responds to the question où est
la chose?, Où est la montagne Sainte Victoire?,
by saying pas de où ponctuel. Le où est
toujours anticipé ou dépassé, jamais en un point.
This means then that the previously mentioned Offenheit is
constitutively en haillons. But, is it the
case perhaps that this fragmentary approach to philosophy is
leading us to perceive a new, final silence? The philosophical
question is not hushed up; it forever begins anew.
LISCIANI-PETRINI -
Activity/Passivity: The Invisible of Merleau-Ponty
If there is a concern which runs through all of
Merleau-Ponty's work, it is that which is first elaborated in The
Structure of Behavior: the return to a total picture of
reality made up not of things,
articulated objects, or substances, but rather of lines of force. In other words, for the
French philosopher, one is trying from the beginning to arrive at
a view of the world seen not as substantial reality,
but rather as a system of related concordances.
One of the theoretical starting points for this strand of
thinking is the particular case of hands touching
each other an example taken, significantly, from Husserl.
In fact, this phenomenon, with its specific sort of
reversibility, shows that each relational pole finds
its true identity through the other, starting from the
other. Therefore from a kind of reflection, an
uninterrupted exchange proceeds from one to the other. All of
this allows us to glimpse a kind of connection (which had been
completely unknown) in which the poles are not there, do
not pre-exist (they cannot pre-exist) the relationship
itself.
Here begins an ontological vision that is genuinely new, a
vision in which the concepts of substance,
material, identity, time, and
space can no longer function. Now reality is
presented as a propagation of reflections
(of relationships) in which each element is the
zero-point, the nucleus of absence in
which the rays of the world meet one another.
But, here a vertiginous procedure really begins.
If the world is a diffuse pattern of already present
reflections (in act), then no one can explain why it happens, why this pattern exists: it is
given. Just as in the particular case of hands
touching each other in which it is impossible to
coincide with the moment in which the hand that is
being touched gives itself as passive material for
the activity of the other hand that precise moment in
fact, if reflexively considered, has already become
something constituted, in act. This is,
therefore, the background which cannot be brought to
reflection the true invisible
on which, literally, the whole activity flow
diffused in the world is suspended.
In the end, on the basis of the whole relationship, there is a
synthesis always already given, that
is, a passivity which needs to be rethought in relation to
activity in order to understand completely activity's absolute
insubstantiality. In other words, the world is
suspended in one possibility to
put it in classical Aristotelian terms, in one
potency that as a matter of
principle is hidden by the reflection itself. A
possible therefore conceived not as another
eventual occurence (Themes from the Lectures at the
Collège de France 1952-1960, p. 98), but is
endured by the thought of not being able to go
beyond itself. In its being, thought is, therefore, always
only activity which cannot in any way provide a basis
for itself, and which is made up of an instability which
threatens from within. This is the problem that Merleau-Ponty
summarizes in this concise but clear statement: Philosophy
has never spoken I do not say of passivity: we are not
effects but I would say of the passivity of our
activity (The Visible and the Invisible, p. 221,
my emphasis).
FRANZINI - Painting and
Difference
In the history of the theories of Western painting, the
Byzantine debate on iconoclasm opens the question of the visible
and the invisible. Worship is not directed ultimately at images,
because images have less reality than what they represent. In
fact, the image is the reflection of an invisible Prototype. So,
when Merleau-Ponty thinks about this relation, he wants perhaps
to reflect upon some questions raised from the Neoplatonic
tradition. But his starting point is totally different; he is
conscious of the perceptive reality of the body, which he
defines, in the wake of Herder, as sensorium commune.
So, there is an analogy between Merleau-Ponty and Herder, since
the tactile and visual body is always a unity that is organic,
complete, and synthetic.
Merleau-Ponty's investigation of this pre-categorical unity of
the body leads him to ontology. But, in the circuit of Being,
where there are neither breaks nor particular questions,
Merleau-Ponty runs the risk of losing the symbolic sense of the
work of art as well as its sense as an event. In order to
investigate the symbolic worth of art, we can examine two
iconoclastic positions: that of G. Deleuze and that
of J.-F. Lyotard. Both Deleuze and Lyotard simultaneously
criticize and acknowledge a debt to Merleau-Ponty.
Deleuze criticizes the organic characteristic of the lived
body in Merleau-Ponty; thus, he re-examines the role of tactility
in Herder in order to annihilate the symbolic union of the body.
In turn, Lyotard shows the necessity of suspecting (and of
deconstructing) a philosophy such as that of Merleau-Ponty which
sees itself as a metaphor of ontological unity: the event of art
can be situated only in the free space opened by desire.
The two positions are perhaps excessive in their radicality,
because a categorical definition of the nature of art
disperses its intuitive particularity. But the theoretical
positions of Deleuze and Lyotard nevertheless allow us to
understand the aesthetical variety of the artistic form and the
ambiguity of its temporal dimension. The time, the rhythm of
time, is the essential plot of the symbolic character that
belongs to the spatial reality of the images of the painting.
BARBARAS - Merleau-Ponty at the Limits of Phenomenology
It seems at first glance that phenomenology and cosmology are
mutually exclusive. Phenomenology starts from an insurmountable
eidetic difference between consciousness and reality, whereas
cosmology is based on a decision which defines Being in a way
which is neutral in regard to objectivity and subjectivity. If
this is the case, then how can we understand the fact that
Merleau-Ponty claims to provide a cosmology of the
visible? Would the radicality of what phenomenology
requires lead to a filling-in of this gap between consciousness
and reality? Would it itself lead the way to its own
transformation into cosmology?
Husserlian phenomenology is grounded on a presupposition that
it never thematizes and that it shares with the metaphysical
tradition. It considers Being from a previous Nothingness; such
an approach means that Being is defined as the negation of
Nothingness. This is the reason why, for this tradition, essence defines the ontological meaning of what exists. Only what can be
defined thoroughly is able to surmount nothingness. This is also
the reason why this philosophy comes to completion in
transcendental phenomenology: to define presence as a
presentation of the thing itself amounts to a positing of
consciousness as the place of this presentation. So, Husserl's
approach does not escape from being a pensée de survol.
From the viewpoint of this surveying thought, it
nevertheless condemns cosmology.
In contrast, Merleau-Ponty's reduction consists in
neutralizing the presupposition of nothingness. It does not go
from the natural world to consciousness but from nothingness to
the phenomenal world as what is already there. Now, insofar as
the world no longer negates a previous nothingness, it accepts
into itself a negativity. This negativity comes from the fact
that the world is given by remaining distant, that its visibility
includes a part of irreducible invisibility. That is why the
positivity of consciousness is criticized: the distance which is
peculiar to experience does not result from its subjective
character, but is constitutive of the being which can be attained
through this experience. Subjectivity no longer refers to a
singular being, but is a characteristic of Being, since it
appears in the light of presence by means of stepping back into
depth. In this way, the eidetic gap between consciousness and
reality is filled-in so that Being includes both transcendence
and subjectivity as its inner dimensions.
How can we account for the ontological meaning of this Being,
which is identity in difference, in other words,
which is excess or withdrawal? How can we give a sense to this
invisible, this dimension of manifestation which is not different
from the visible but nevertheless not identical to it? We suggest
that this Being be characterized as the virtual as Deleuze
defines this term, namely, as that whose reality is a task to be
achieved and acquires actuality by producing differences. Insofar
as the being of the invisible, defined as the virtual, is not
different from its operation, it is able to realize itself as
visible without merging with it. The self-distance that
characterizes the Being disclosed by the reduction must be
thought, in a dynamical way, as a virtuality that becomes actual
through differences and whose virtuality is maintained by this
becoming actual. Essence as virtuality, the principle of
actuality, replaces essence as possibility which is opposed to
reality.
With this idea of Being, we reveal an element that is more
originary than the opposition between subjectivity and
objectivity. And, therefore, we are in a position to conceive a
cosmology. This dimension of virtuality cannot be thought as a
real being existing beyond the realm of experience; the cosmology
is always a cosmology of the visible world; the monism it
expresses is phenomenological rather than metaphysical. So,
Merleau-Ponty is placed at the limit of phenomenology in a double
sense: insofar as he completes what phenomenology requires, he is
located at the boundary between phenomenology and cosmology; he
blurs their very opposition.
CARBONE - The
Mythical Time of Ideas: Merleau-Ponty and Deleuze as
Readers of Proust
Only a few years separate Merleau-Ponty's remarks on Proust's Recherche found in The Visible and the Invisible as well as in
preparatory notes to the course entitled L'ontologie
cartésienne et l'ontologie d'aujourd'hui (1960-61) and the
original edition of Deleuze's Proust and Signs (1964).
Nevertheless, even if these two readings are essentially focused
on Proust's conception of essences or
ideas, and even if both end with finding the truth of
the sensible in art, they are actually more symmetrical than
convergent. This lack of convergence also reveals the different
ways in which Leibniz influences especially through his
notion of total part Merleau-Ponty's thought
(but also, in my opinion, Proust's work) and Proust's work as
Deleuze interprets it. Indeed, Merleau-Ponty is inclined to judge
art as an achievement of our common belonging to the sensible and
to assimilate the ideas of art to sensible ideas,
which he considers to be prior to the opposition between
individual essences and universal essences. In contrast, Deleuze
prefers to emphasize the discontinuity between sensible
sign and artistic sign, devoting himself less
to the search for the link which still must join the two since,
in his opinion, the latter is the truth of the former. Thus, he
points out that essences are absolutely individual
only in the artistic signs, while in the
sensible signs the essences maintain a minimum
of generality. Furthermore, on the one hand, Merleau-Ponty
seems to define the time in which sensible ideas live as a
mythical time, which he characterizes by the invasion
of succession by simultaneity so that certain events `in
the beginning' maintain a continued efficacity;
Deleuze, on the other hand, clearly distinguishes between an
original and identical to eternity time,
revealed only by the artistic signs, and a lost time that is
found, on the contrary, through the sensible signs.
Even though a general examination inevitably tends to
highlight the divergences existing between the different readings
of Recherche made by Deleuze and Merleau-Ponty,
nevertheless we can see some remarkable convergences when we
think about the Deleuze's characterization of Proust's
sensible idea that he has more widely examined: the
idea of Combray (the in itself of Combray) seen in
its essential relationship with its own temporality, and analyzed
especially in Difference and Repetition where, in turn,
Deleuze defines the time in which this in itself
lives as a past that was never present and that tends
all the same to propose itself as an ancient mythical present. If we think together Merleau-Ponty's
characterization of the sensible idea and Deleuze's
characterization of the in itself of Combray, then we are able to
understand that the former is a dimension that can never
again be closed only because, simultaneously, it also
founds a prior life which will always permeate its
own process of resumptions and recommencements. In turn, this
allows us to avoid the Platonism that the clear-cut separation
between the time of the artistic and the time of the sensible
signs Deleuze makes in Proust and Signs seems to reveal;
moreover this allows us to acknowledge that ideas have a body this is precisely the mythical time in
virtue of which we can no longer assimilate the
initiation to a metaphysical beginning. In
other words, this allows us to comprehend that, with his notions
of sensible ideas and of initiation,
Merleau-Ponty was trying to bring to blossom, in his ontology, a
thought that is, after all, not so different than the
transcendental empiricism which Deleuze describes in Difference
and Repetition as an exotic and subversive plant.
GAMBAZZI - The
Fission of Being, Essences, and Absolute Visibility:
Individuation and the Haecceity of the Thing in the Later
Merleau-Ponty
I would like to ask several questions which concern an
important problem in Merleau-Ponty's ontology: the same as the
other rather than the other as the other, identity as the
difference of difference.
Merleau-Ponty's last writings have opened a field of
philosophical interrogation within which Being as explosion, as
non-coincidence, as differentiation, is located. Presence is
originarily divergence (écart). One must therefore
conceive of a strange distance of the subject from
itself and of the thing from its own identity. The things are
neither identical to themselves nor substantial atoms. They are
variants of other things and other spatio-temporal positions.
Differentiation is also a modulation. Therefore, while differing,
the things are however absolutely together. There is
a cohesion between them which turns them into extreme
differences, extreme divergences of one sole something.
One must therefore find a response to the following questions:
Why are there several samples of each thing?. Why is
perception a differentiation-integration, a
`montage' of one universal, diacritical system? This system
is not an originary model which founds multiplicity, and to
perceive is not to represent.
What is being asked here is the question of infinity. We have
to start to ask this question in relation to the following
extreme formulation that we find in Merleau-Ponty: Visibility in
itself is formed as upon two mirrors facing one another
where two indefinite series of images set in one another arise
which belong to neither of the the surfaces, since each is only
the rejoinder of the other, and which therefore form a couple, a
couple more real than either of them.
The absence of a model upsets the status of the
Form. Individuation is not established through a type
of modeling, but by a modulation (Simondon). We cannot prioritize
either the principle of individuation nor the individual being.
The thingness of the thing and the truth of the subject are
essentially somewhere below unity and identity. The thing is a Seinsgeschick and the subject is anonymous.
All of this radically puts individuation into question. There
are modes of individuation which are no longer those of a
thing, of a person, or of a subject: for example, the
individuation of an hour of the day, of a region, of a climate,
of a flower, or a breeze, of an event (Deleuze).
The concept must say the event, and no longer the essence. In
"Everywhere and Nowhere Merleau-Ponty writes that one
has to open up the concept without destroying it, and
in The Visible and the Invisible he argues that
Being is what requires creation of us for us to
experience it.
CASSOU-NOGUES - Towards
a Merleau-Pontean Epistemology in Mathematics
The aim of this paper is to lay out some principles for an
epistemology of mathematics based on, or at least coherent with,
Merleau-Ponty's later writings, notably The Prose of the World and The Visible and the Invisible. In these texts,
Merleau-Ponty has moved on from his famous dismissal of science
in The Phenomenology of Perception. However, it seems he
still fails to capture the true creativity of mathematical
thinking. Therefore, we use Cavaillès' philosophy of science,
and then apply to mathematics the concept of expression that
Merleau-Ponty defines for language, painting and perception.
Finally, we introduce the problem of physics.
GRILLO - The Subject at the
Mirror: Merleau-Ponty, Derrida, and Valéry Starting from Qual
Quelle
Qual Quelle, Derrida's 1971 essay on the problem of the
sources in Valéry, analyzes the problem of
the origin in a way similar to that of Merleau-Ponty: the origin
can no longer be considered as fullness and presence of sense to
itself. For Derrida, the origin is a result issuing from the play
of différance; for Merleau-Ponty, the origin presents
itself as a certain emptiness, hollow, or fissure in the
interlacing of the world and the corporeal self, an emptiness
which allows for the birth of the world and its dimensions of
sense.
In Valéry, Derrida discovers that it is impossible for
consciousness to constitute itself and see itself: the subject
can return to itself only by losing itself in the mirror. The
self is therefore always slipping, always doubling itself; it is
difference and identity at the same time, interruption of the
circuit between me and myself. All of Derrida's expressions,
however, are similar to those employed by Merleau-Ponty in The
Visible and the Invisible. The body touches itself touching,
sees itself seeing in a coincidence that is, however, always in
the future and never accomplished. Every vision, especially one's
vision of oneself, is marked by a certain invisibility, a certain
blindness; this blindness represents the logic of the
self-portrait in Derrida's Memoirs of the Blind and
the narcissism of the flesh in Merleau-Ponty's The
Visible and the Invisible, as Robert Vallier emphasizes. But,
how can we consider sense in a form other than that of presence?
The problem consists in how one interprets the
unconscious. Derrida explains Valéry's refusal of
the unconscious as a refusal of sense as such; but Valéry does
not refuse sense, he refuses sense considered as
fond, as ground, as content existing independently
from the process of expression that produces it. Merleau-Ponty
had profoundly studied this criticism of the concept of meaning
with premises similar to those of Derrida; but, in Merleau-Ponty,
they become the possibility of another way of understanding
sense. Sense is not the subject's possession; it is explosion and
dimensionality of being; it is the frame of being, which gives
itself only at a distance and never by coincidence. So, for
Merleau-Ponty, differentiation's activity is not an unspeakable
origin, as it is for Derrida, but an articulation which is not
nothing, an articulation by means of which sense arises. |